Saturday, March 5, 2022

The Philosophy of War and Exile: From the Humanity of War to the Inhumanity of Peace. Nolen Gertz.

 The Philosophy of War and Exile: From the Humanity of War to the Inhumanity of Peace. 

Gertz, Nolen
2014 
 Plagrave Studies in Ethics and Public Policy

--------------------------------

Below is a real conversation between me and a friend, which took place in early February 2022:

-       Man, you are hypervigilant now. This is a sign of anxiety. Keep calm. Control yourself better, or visit a psychoanalyst, I said.

-       You might be right from a certain perspective. But let me reverse it [your argument]. The thing that you see as anxiety is the sign of vigilance. Not vice versa. I have peace without any anxiety . . . name it craziness . . . name it anxiety. I do not care.

 This conversation summarizes the book idea, I would argue.

 

Nolen Gertz in his book, The Philosophy of War and Exile, unveils the meaning of and the relations between three concepts: everyday life, the common morality, and exile or anxiety as an existential experience. Everyday life is our worldly home where we, human beings, conceive of familiarity, safety, and certainty in/of this world. But this home is, in fact, nothing but a mask. It is a mask clouding the Self’s eye, refraining it from seeing the reality as it is; we are confused or, perhaps, deceived as we see this everyday-home as equal to the world. The world and the everyday-home become equivalent, their shapes are the same, their spaces are equal, and so are their essence. This is an illusion.  Our everyday-home is made in the world, but it is never the world. 


 

The everyday life/home rests on common morality gluing human beings with a feeling of certainty. In other words, the everyday life produces and is produced by common morality, a set of beliefs, values, premises, and cognitive schemata. We walk, work, sleep, and argue everyday in a way that conforms to and confirms these set’s elements, the common morality. Common morality, therefore, is carved out to channel our brains and hearts (to form the common, the sharable): What I see is exactly what you see, how I evaluate a phenomenon or an event is so similar to how you do.  A man suffering from anxiety is a “deviant” man from the normal. A woman, in a traditional society, disobeying her husband is a “deviant” woman from the normal, the basic, the common morality.


 
 

 

 Read about this woman on Wikipedia











When you see a bird, you believe that this “flying-singing-beautiful-thing” has been there, in the nature, in its world, forever. You are certain about it. The existence of that bird (or of Bird as a universal category) and its beauty is certain. Similarly, common morality makes us think of our social world, our societies, as certain as this bird. I see what you see, I evaluate in the same way you do, so our common world is real, is there, is right. Other ways of seeing and evaluating are deviant, sick, unreal, and illusionary. Common morality is certainty’s producer.  



 

The third concept is exile. Not everyone can accept or submit herself to the common morality; i.e., some individuals or groups can be only “deviant.” Ideas or beliefs that the majority of us take as premises, absolutely true, are simply untrue, non-logical, or ideas that can be discussed and modified for those who can only be deviant. Why some people are like this? Because of exile. Exile, in this vein, is not a place to where prisoners are ousted. It is a metaphor, a concept, alluding to what does not belong to the common morality, and it is a living metaphor (as much as a cow is a living being) enabling people to reject the common morality of their societies. If we stick to this spatial analogy, then exile is what lies outside the common morality’s space, on the edge of what is known to be a human enjoying her certainty about the world.

Exile à Anxiety

When you come from the exile, you do not fit into the realm of certainty (attested by the common morality), so you experience anxiety and radiate anxiety among others. What is used to be a beautiful bird for others, is not so anymore for you. It is something else. You, now, are alone. You are detached from the world and its everyday-home, so you are homeless. This existential anxiety is the exile flag, its marker. To be more precise, exile is a locus of anxiety, not as a sickness, but a way of being in the world.

 

Anxiety à a way of being in the world; Everyday-home the World

Certainty à a way of being in the world; Everyday-home = the World

 

Fencing the Exile, Curbing the Anxiety, Protecting Our Home

We fight this exile, curbing it, and preventing it from seeping into our “known” world and morality to sustain our certainty and to keep the resulted anxiety away from our everyday-home. How do we so? By labeling this exile and the people coming from it, feeding themselves from it, as deviant, sick, insane, and needy for medical care. We bend exile-agents to fit into our common knowledge:

-       No sir, this thing, flying, singing . . . is a bird. You do not see it as a bird, then I will drive you to a hospital so they apply their knowledge-power to cure you; very soon, you will see it as a bird again, or you will be kept captive behind the hospital wall until your death.

This imagined talk has the exact power (power of logic, power of common sense, power of knowledge) of the conversation that I had with my friend:

-       Man, you are hypervigilant now. This is a sign of anxiety. Keep calm. Control yourself better, or visit a psychoanalyst, I said.

-       You might be right from a certain perspective. But let me reverse it [your argument]. The thing that you see as anxiety is the sign of vigilance. Not vice versa. I have peace without any anxiety . . . name it craziness . . . name it anxiety. I do not care.

My friend has just come from exile. He is now connected to it, speaks of it, and from it he drinks, eats, and thinks. I tried to tell him you are crazy. I did so to protect my everyday-home, the common morality and to keep myself isolated from anxiety (although, indeed, I am super “anxious,” and a super cursed exile’s man). He, on the other hand, pursued invading our (not only my) world, the known world, the home (more precisely) with the exile he had discovered.

This exile is, however, what we should embrace not expel, to welcome not fear. It is a (or maybe the) the source of nourishing our humanity and our potential, whereas the common morality is what refrains us from doing so. That is, exile opens new horizons for the Self to be. It creates. Common morality and the constant restoration to the everyday-home is cowardice; it imprisons the Self. 



 The Self shrouded into the common morality and the everyday-home is rooted or grounded into this world enjoying a high level of certainty, exactly as these plants in the picture happily rooted (Prairie Studies, John Earnest Weaver, University of Nebraska 1932-52). They hold their ground, their roots in the world, so they are certain about themselves. Exile uproots their roots, shakes up their ground, telling them, “Your roots are only a part of the world, of the reality, and you can expand your roots in other directions; you, dear plants, can even walk.”


These plants (analogy of the Self) conceive the space into which their roots are grounded as the world. Exile, a deviant plant/Self, unmasks this illusion. The roots occupy a part of the possible world; that is the reality.

We need to live the experience of exile because it reveals to us the reality as it is; in that, incommensurability is more real than commonality (the common morality), and an open-ended and ever-unfolding world is more real than a close-ended world.

This call for welcoming anxiety, emanating from exile, and the call for opening our Selves are elaborated on through three cases in this book: veterans’ PTSD, torture as a way to fight terrorism, and unmanned drones as a means of war.

Serene Everyday life, home. Painting by Paul Fischer. 


Understanding instead of Judging

A veteran coming back from a war zone (in a Western country, the US as the prevalent empirical base for the author’s argument) is diagnosed by other people, by the authority, the medical authority as endorsing PTSD when he fails to reintegrate back in the zone of peace, in the everyday life (home) that is distinctive essentially from the life of war. The inability of a veteran to draw a clear line between peace and war, between acting normally in the zone of peace and abnormally in the zone of war is seen as illness: A veteran suffers from PTSD, he is a deviant, he invades our home (the peace zone) with things/feelings/actions that belong to the war zone. He invades our everyday-home with the exile (the exile that was generated in the war zone). We, the people who are instructed about PTSD, try to help that veteran to be back to the normal, to the everyday life of peace. As we do so, he feels more and more alienated. We neither understand him nor he does understand our world. We ask him to be “normal,” but normality for him is no more what we understand. The fact that suicide rate is extremely high among veterans in the US is not, therefore, a result of less-professionality to treat PTSD veterans, but it is a result of our persistence to see veterans as patients of PTSD, as deviants.

We impose a picture that our world, our everyday life, is well grounded, resting on our common morality, and veterans are the groundless because they were immersed in a war that – by its nature – subverts the common morality (through the action of killing, see below Box 1), so they fail to re-integrate in the “common morality,” simply because they have subverted it during the fighting. Hence, they become alienated (exiled, uprooted) and anxious.

But veterans are not those who are the groundless, but our world is. What we think of as a ground is nothing but an illusion. The veterans know that because they had experienced the exile. We did not.

Thus, common morality assures an essential commonality on which our humanity becomes possible. But what if commonality is just an illusion, a suppression of otherness, and what if incommensurability is on which our humanity should be (and in reality is) dwelled. In other words, the everyday-home is the soil of communality where we are what we are; everything is fixed and certain. Exile is the soil of incommensurability, where otherness and openness, becoming and thriving allow us to change what we already are and to become what we can be.




Box 1   



A veteran knows that what he does in war is killing, and killing is against common morality, and that his state has trained him to justify killing enemies in the light of morality. A veteran would easily ask himself if killing other human beings in a battlefield is justified morally, why then is not everything also justified in the “normal” everyday life? The distinction between good and evil, between war and peace becomes blurred. A veteran kills, but the others, the non-combatants, do not. They assume that what belongs to war is just ephemeral. A veteran does not share with them this belief. For non-combatants, war is ephemeral – in terms of morality – because it denigrates human conditions (we have to fight, we do not have another choice!), whereas a veteran believes that the denigrated nature of human beings is what produces war and what makes its condition possible, not vice versa. As a result, a veteran develops a different view and understanding of the world; he now sees what we call common morality, everyday normal life, from his exile. We reject to admit this exile as a real realm. So, we categorize that veteran as sick suffering PTSD. We judge him. Instead of looking at our world, our humanity from his own eyes, from the exile, we enforce him into our commonality again. We often fail, he kills himself. 

What we must do is to allow for this exile to be alive, to admit the incommensurability (so, otherness, the differences, etc.) so we develop, improve our human conditions. This endeavour kindles anxiety, but we are already suffused with anxiety. The problem is not preventing anxiety but stopping to flee from it. We need to embrace it, so the Self is open and thrives, is becoming rather than is what it is (p.63).   




 

How Soldiers/Veterans Enter the Exile?

Soldiers enter wars and kill others because they experience ecstasy. Warring as an institutional action is ecstatic: A self is absorbed by a “bigger” reality than itself, by the outside that surrounds it, which might be the command, the comrades, the fighting itself. This ecstasy yielded by war is located out of the common moral realm; thus, it is neither moral nor immoral, it is amoral. Ecstasy penetrates the boundaries of the Self, exposing it to be absorbed into the world around. This process is not psychological, merely, but it exists in the reality of the war; it is natural in its existence as much a tree is natural in its existence and not merely a psychological perception: if “something can be attacked it must be attacked” (p.51).  This is the ecstasy’s  “natural existence.” As a soldier attacks what is, by its own, attackable, he loses himself into the realm of war, into the command and the relation with comrades, and he leaves the realm of morality. His conscience is silenced, and he is not responsible for what he/they/the nature of war does. He experiences this “amazing” feeling of making the Self absorbed in a “higher,” an outer reality.


Liberty Leading the People by Delacroix, 1830, materializes what war’s ecstasy is.

However, once this soldier or veteran receives a command to kill and suddenly recognizes that he, his Self, can disobey the order and cease killing, his conscience comes back from the realm of ecstasy to the realm of responsibility. He and his actions become im/moral again. He looks at the killing, the horror there in front of his eyes, and feels guilty. However, this is not his own guilt, but the guilt of the world, the state, the system, the human being itself which made this war possible, the guilt of the possibility – for us as human beings – to experience this ecstasy by warring (metaphysical guilt).  Now, instead of being absorbed, the Self is disconnected from anything. This disconnectedness’s anxiety should be assuaged. It can be so only by putting the conscience to silence again. However, this time silencing the consciousness cannot be achieved by ecstasy anymore (the light of awareness is there, no absence into a higher reality). The disconnectedness must pitter out; how? only more war and more engagement in destroying others can silence the soldier’s responsibility, the moral awareness, his metaphysical guilt. When the war is over, how can we, the bearers of the common morality, ask the now-veteran to come back to the peace zone, to the home of humanity. If we do not admit the exile he revealed and lived, he never comes back to be like us.

This responsibility, the anxiety that humans are all apt to endure (and we really do as we, the common morality bearers, design wars and justify them, designate military, and invent nation states), “is best understood as a matter of identity rather than morality,” so we accept the exile as a place into which our identity (not reducing it into morality) can grow, blossom: “we must become becoming” rather than being that “we are who we are” (p.63). 

On Torture

Torture is not a moral issue to be questioned whether it is right or wrong in case of investigating a terrorist hiding a bomb and aiming to kill thousands of innocents. It is a matter of identity (p.83). This what we will elaborate on.

Torture is not a personal action; rather, it is institutional. A recruited person, who will be a torturer later, is integrated into an institution, which will be seen as the moral agency by which the responsibility of torture is hefted. Entering this institution, voluntarily or not (by kidnapping, for example), is masqueraded with an illusion of free choice. The recruited is given a choice: either he becomes a member in this institution, or he faces his fate, which could be death. As the recruited chooses joining and integration in the institution, he seems as if he had freely chosen to do so. He had the choice to leave, but he preferred to stay. This choice will be later the choice of being a torturer instead of being tortured or dead (torture is a matter of identity not morality).

Being a torturer, after institutionalization, requires training or routinization. A torturer himself passes through torture, watches torture videos, so he isolates his feelings from his later actions (torture), and he takes torture as a duty, a moral duty: If I could stand pain, he tells himself, then a tortured person can do so.

This process of torture is competed by dehumanizing both the tortured and the torturer. It is the empirical fact both of them suffer from similar traumatic symptoms. Torture as a process of denigrating human beings, similarly to a war experience, forms a re-transformation of dehumanization, eternally passing, between the tortured and the torturer.

Torture should be/is a matter of identity not morality because it is imposed forcefully into our common morality (understanding) as torture of the body not of the soul. It is your body what was tortured not the real you. It is impossible for whoever to torture the real you. This understanding or framing of torture dwells on the dualism doctrine of mind/body, human/universe, the Cartesian doctrine. However, this dualism is not real. The tortured is - really - his body and his body becomes everything as he is fumbling into pain. It is not that, as we are pushed to believe, the body of the tortured is a façade of his real identity, and it is not that death embraces only the flesh while the soul is untouchable, and it is not that pain can pass because it is less real than the mind/soul (under the umbrella of dualism). The dualist doctrine frames responsibility of a wrongdoing (e.g., torture) as something attached to an action, so it is easily isolable from our normal, common life. It is a wrongdoing, simply an action, simply belonging to the body not the real you. So, do not worry, it is an exemption of the everyday life, and the common morality is still clean from this wrongdoing; and we are irresponsible for what some of us have done. But no. The responsibility of wrongdoing is not a feature of actions, it is us. It is our identity.

When we ask a tortured to forgive or forget, or when we ask a torturer to justify his torture by the morality of saving innocents, we prevent the exile from showing us our own identity, as human being, as the real responsible of torture. It is our commonality and our present human conditions, which make torture possible.  Again, that is why torture is a matter of identity not morality: It is we, not our morality, which tortures. It is we, not the lack of morality, which makes us suffer. We are the suffering, we are the responsibility, Gertz firmly stresses.



NOTE: The author discusses unmanned drones and their usage in war, contending that drone operators suffer from trauma as much as those who fight at real fronts. However, I will not discuss it here.

Finally . . .

Everyone of us should be the veteran experiencing anxiety and exile: Through anxiety the “I” is unmasked and comes under the spot of reflection. Anxiety is not a feeling we pass through, but it is who we are (p.143). Martin Luther King is seen (through the same logic of seeing PTSD veterans and torture as an exemption/ephemeral/outsider), as an exemplar. He is not. He should not be. He is like as anyone of us, who could enter the exile and see what is real about our own identity (not morality) as humans.


For a better view, click here.
 






No comments:

Post a Comment

Book: Refugia: Radical solutions to mass displacement (Robin Cohen and Nicholas Van Hear), 2020

  Refugia This book utilizes a novel methodology, utopianism, to discuss and analyze the problem of refugees. It is, therefore, critically e...